What is the difference between status and class




















Not a member? Sign up for My OBO. Already a member? Publications Pages Publications Pages. Subscriber sign in You could not be signed in, please check and try again. Username Please enter your Username. Password Please enter your Password. Forgot password? Don't have an account?

Sign in via your Institution. You could not be signed in, please check and try again. Sign in with your library card Please enter your library card number. Related Articles Expand or collapse the "related articles" section about About Related Articles close popup.

Your current browser may not support copying via this button. It also refers to the level of honour, respect, and deference accorded to a person. Some people have a better social status than others. Social status can be ascribed or achieved. Moreover, sex, age, family relationships, religion, and race are usually the basis of an ascribed relationship. For example, we consider a person born to a poor family to have a low social status.

However, some people also achieve social status through their skills, abilities, and efforts. This may be based on factors like education, job, accomplishments, and marital status. For example, if someone belongs to lower status by birth, but he gets a good education and a prestigious job, he will achieve a better social status in society. In a society, people usually use the hierarchy of social status to allocate resources, positions of leadership and other forms of power. How do they do this?

By any objective standard, their capacity to deal with the routine injuries and illnesses are quite similar—and both doctors and nurses are quite capable of making competent diagnoses, and prescribing treatment.

But of course only doctors legitimately do this, a right that is protected by the legal order. And despite competencies that are similar in an objective fashion, the lower ranked Stand that is, nurses are paid less and are assumed to be less competent, whereas the higher ranked Stand that is, doctors are paid better and assumed to have special competencies—even if they do not.

The ideologies of the two professions reflect these hierarchical relationships, with the doctors needing to explain why they naturally have more rights and money than nurses, and the subordinated nurses needing to explain why they receive less money, have fewer rights, but also have hidden honour. As for the legitimating ideology itself, doctors focus on their glorious past: grades in college, biochemistry courses, rigour of the medical schooling training and the solemnity of the Hippocratic Oath.

For nurses, the emphasis is on day-to-day contact with patients, on-the-job competencies and the obvious fact that the work of the hospital is dependent on their constant presence and not that of doctors who are often absent and only make periodic rounds.

To maintain exclusivity, doctors and nurses cultivate different symbols, routines and rituals. Among these are different uniforms, badges and vocabulary that sustain stereotypes about relative competence—doctors are assumed by doctors anyway to be cerebral, wise and skilled, whereas nurses are assumed to be practical but perhaps a bit impulsive and certainly not as cerebral.

Dominant doctors assume this relationship to be natural and a function of the rigourous training doctors undertake to gain entry into an ancient profession, even as some doctors become alcoholics and drug addicts as they age.

And indeed when such things do happen, care is taken that the fellow doctor is protected from the broader legal system and dealt with internally by the Stand. As for nurses, they might see doctors as impetuous prima donnas, careless and unaware of the very human needs of the patients.

They also see doctors as overpaid—and nurses secretly hope that one day their true honour will finally be recognized, and they will get a big raise. Such are the stereotypes of hospital-based anthropological purebreds that persist as beliefs about relative competence and incompetence. Now, the case of doctors and nurses is a convenient way to think about this distinction because professional lines are so carefully drawn, particularly in the relatively confined world of a hospital.

Thus administrators are housed in separate buildings, and use separate bathrooms. Students meanwhile have exclusive access to dormitory-based dining commons from which faculty are excluded. Faculty dining clubs are similarly exclusive, except for the students present as subordinated wait staff.

Administrators have private parking places, and are unlikely to eat in front of either group. As Goffman describes, sustaining exclusivity of the established hierarchical order and avoiding embarrassment that mixing implies are important for maintaining the hierarchy.

Indeed, in the world of the modern university, there are even explicit rules about exogamous sexual relationships between faculty and undergraduate students that are enforced both via the legal order in the United States, as well as through normative feelings of disgust by faculty and students alike.

Such principles of professional exclusivity apply to bakers, soldiers, barbers, lawyers, teachers, taxi drivers, truck drivers, that is, any professional Stand that seeks to include and exclude on the basis of rituals designed to preserve their style of life.

In such contexts, exclusivity via norms regarding dress, language use, professional activities and so on emerged. Such relationships are often defined by kinship terms, and used to justify the arrangement of endogamous marriages. Dress and other distinctions, with distinctive jackets, kilts, hats, badges and other symbolic signifiers emerge to highlight residential distinctions.

In modern times, this might include the wearing of the sports jersey from a favourite team, or in the case of Texans, a cowboy hat and boots. In turn, this is reflected in norms about endogamy and exogamy, which have the effect of maintaining rights to the land, grazing rights, guild membership and other claims to economic privilege based on residency.

Distinctive claims about assignment and assertion emerge in the social context of the group Cornell and Hartmann, : 19— This happened despite the availability of other salient identities such as Hanoverian, Hessian, Prussian, Bavarian or Swabian. What these examples have in common is a context of European migration and a need to establish an identity relative to a pre-existing dominant majority. Or as Weber writes:. Persons who are externally different are simply despised irrespective of what they accomplish or what they are, or they are venerated superstitiously if they are too powerful in the long run.

In this case antipathy is the primary and normal reaction. In the United States, Weber writes, this is the origin of racist ideologies that metastasize after the destruction of the caste-based slave labour system at the end of the Civil War, re-emerging as the beliefs, habitus , norms and laws that protected exclusivity and advantage for the dominant white Stand.

Context-dependent definitions of skin colour and hierarchy persisted in this context despite legal changes. Footnote 16 In British Malaya, a similar process developed further, even after the British departed Hirschmann, In this context, US American whites and blacks developed persistent cultures rooted in the positive and negative privileges emerging from the racial caste system.

The ideologies that emerged among the whites explained the historical origins of the status quo by defining the privileges of race—the result being self-fulfilling prophecies describing how privilege of the present are a natural outgrowth of the heroism of the past. At the same time, negatively privileged blacks developed a strong culture highlighting the fact that American institutions from southern plantations to the modern military are dependent on the skills and labour of subordinated blacks.

Indeed, it is in such contexts that messiah-like figures like Abraham Lincoln and Martin Luther King, Jr emerged from the Gemeinschaft , as well as demands for the legal protection by the federal government of civil rights, especially voting rights. This is perhaps why social segregation is so persistent today, despite the emergence of messianic figures like Martin Luther King, Jr and decades of legal-rational change in the rational institutions of the Gesellschaft.

Social and legal structures underpinning durable Stand -based division of labour is mediated, Weber writes, by rituals focussed on purity. The system in India was and is an extreme case, as Weber notes.

The United States and South Africa had particularly strong race-based caste systems in which racial groups were assigned specific tasks by law within the division of labour.

Merchant minorities such as the Chinese of Southeast Asia, the Indians of East Africa and the Lebanese of West Africa were also thought of in such caste-based contexts. Certainly this applies to ethnic groups, language communities, and sexual minorities. Gender as a socially constructed category is found in every known society and has implications everywhere for inequality, particularly in the context of patriarchy. Monkhoods, sororities, fraternities, militaries, cabarets, dance troupes, sports teams, age-cohorts, employers and so on all use gender explicitly as the primary a basis for inclusion and exclusion.

Many other groups use gendered identities as a marker of exclusivity as well. Relations between male and female can be intimate and also unequal. And within most gender-based Stand groups, preserving exogamy between male and female does not always make much sense! What examples from his day were relevant? Weber uses as an example the propertyless who come under the control of the cattle breeders, such as slaves or serfs.

In such context, he writes, the honour of the Stand apportioned by the Gemeinschaft becomes the most important source of distinction for the distribution of life chances Giddens, : Few situations matched the abject poverty of serfdom and slavery in the modern world, except maybe prisons where prisoners lack property altogether.

Now, of course, Weber does not write of prisons. The distribution of tasks in the Hindu caste system is, for Weber, a good example of this. As for positive privilege, Weber develops an odd illustration from European duelling practices that illustrates Stand privilege well. Thus, it was unthinkable for a noble to issue a duel challenge to peasant, or vice versa. Such stories Weber writes are why so many Americans claimed descent from Pocohontas of Virginia, and the Pilgrim Fathers in New England rather than presumably New England merchants and southern cotton dealers.

In developing these examples, Weber emphasizes that, even though the accumulation of money occurred in the anonymous and despised marketplace of the past, the desire for exclusivity and honour meant that a privileged new Stand emerged in which financial activity was viewed as beneath their level, in the same fashion Weber noted for the Indian Brahmins.

In Germany Weber observes, the boss and the clerk are clearly subordinated in both the office and outside the office. Bosses never fraternize with their clerk. In contrast in the new United States, although the same subordination and deference existed between the boss and clerk in the office, they might even play billiards together as equals after work.

This situation, Weber claimed, was impossible in the older and more rigidly stratified Stand -based stratification system in Germany where habits of deference extended to all spheres. It is here that the work of resolving the inequality of the capitalist economy, with the contradiction of equality before the law is struggled over see Beteille, : — Thus, you get odd fellows within political parties.

For example, in the United States today, the modern Republican Party is in large part an alliance between the class interests of capitalists for example, the instrumental-rationalists of Wall Street and the interests of Stand -based groups for example, value-rationalist evangelical Christians, and gun owners , whose interests come directly from the value-rational Gemeinschaft.

The shared interest is in seeking power, and this single focus results in dissonant positions in parties. Thus in the modern American Republican party platform, this means that businessmen oppose abortion and support gun rights, and Christian pastors supports price for big agriculture and equate gun rights with freedom.

Power itself, Weber writes, is sought using the instrumental rationality of Gesellschaft. Parties thus seek ideals from the clubby legitimacy of a Gemeinschaft whose putative goals are rooted in the language of morality, at the same time making cold calculating decisions about campaigning and governing in an amoral Gesellschaft where power matters most. The tension between the means and the goals are often incompatible—but as Weber writes, in a political party where the goal is winning and wielding power, this is beside the point.

Stand is an analytical term that encompasses categories such as race, gender, sexuality, language use, professions, immigration status and many others.

Thus if honour, with its roots in the value-laden Gemeinschaft , is assumed to be the root of inequality, greater understanding is had of the enduring structures of inequality. As Weber points out, such values persist even in putatively Gesellschaft -based places where calculation is highlighted, like modern courts of law and the modern marketplace; both law and the market ideally operate sine ira et studio without scorn or partiality.

But this is beside the point. And this for Weber is the tension out of which society emerges and changes. In her American Sociological Review article , Stanford University Professor Cecilia Ridgeway illustrated the importance of status that is, Stand by relating an encounter with a shoeshine man at the San Francisco Airport who wanted his daughter to go to medical school at Stanford University and become a doctor.

The good news is that both the shoeshine man at the San Francisco airport and Professor Ridgeway agree that Medical School at Stanford University is the ultimate expression in cultural competence—in other words, they both are acutely aware of status-based values of the United States, that is, the values of their own American Gemeinschaft. It is unlikely that, for example, a shoeshine man in Dar Es Salaam, Bangkok or Chengdu would make the same comment to Professor Ridgeway, have a similar goal for their child or even be able to talk to Professor Ridgeway in a shared language.

Individuals manoeuvre within such pre-existing systems of stratification. Data sharing is not applicable to this article as no datasets were generated or analysed during the current study. How to cite this article : Waters T and Waters D Palgrave Communications. Baecker wrote about the difficulty translating Gewalt coercive force in Weber. See Ridgeway for a review. It is not just American sociology that has changed. For discussions about the difficulties associated with translating Stand into English, see, for example, Waters and Waters : 37—38 , Tribe : — , Wenger , Roth , Graber Indeed, this word continues to be common even today when describing the responsibilities and privileges of civil servants Beamten , and the Mittelstand which occupies a central role in the German economy.

Clearly they do. This has not caught on, in part we think because in modern English it is primarily associated with modern property law and inheritance, and not inherited social status see Wenger, : —; Dahrendorff, : 7. The word implies a shared sense of community that is reliant on both the coercive power Gewalt of the rulers Herrscher , but is also based in norms of consensual conduct shared by ruler and ruled alike see Max Weber Gesamtausgabe, Abteilung I, Band , p.

This part of Economy and Society is an undeveloped outline. But what Weber seems to be working towards is a theory of modernity which explains how Stand -based stratification persists and even flourishes in the context of property, despite the push towards rationalization emerging from the forces of the Gesellschaft.

Investigation of this particularly cryptic point is important. However doing so goes beyond the central point of this article which is about the incompatibility of the two concepts in English-language sociology. We thank an anonymous referee for bringing this passage to our attention. Thus there is irony in the title: Gemeinschaft is left out, even though it is used in the text almost three times more than Gesellschaft.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000